The statement speaks to a form of artistic autonomy that challenges the conventional performer-audience relationship; it invites reflection on what is deemed essential for performance, and what possibilities emerge when the dynamic is disrupted or reimagined. By focusing on the internal processes of the artist rather than the reception by an audience, we open up a realm of performance that is about the act of creation itself. This aligns with a theatrical philosophy which often prioritises the experience and integrity of the artistic expression over the interaction and response of the audience. A counterpoint to this view is that performance is an event designed for an audience, a form of communication or expression that presupposes a spectator. The presence of an audience, their reactions, and their engagement are typically seen as integral to the event itself, creating a dynamic interplay between the observer and the observed, each influencing the experience of the other. However, the notion that performance is an act of communication that requires both a performer and an audience has been increasingly challenged, particularly in the realms of contemporary theatre, performance art, and digital media. If we consider a performance as an artistic release of self-expression, then it can and does exist without an audience. Artists often create for the sake of the art itself or for personal emotional need, rather than for any anticipated public reception; the act of performing itself transforms the individual artist, irrespective of whether anyone is watching.
But is it a “performance” if nobody is being performed to? A
performance typically refers to a live presentation or artistic exhibition
delivered by one or more artists. This could be a play in a theatre, a musical
recital, a dance showcase, a live painting demonstration, or even a street
artist’s display. Here, performance is characterised by its temporality; it is
an event that happens over time and is designed for an audience to witness and
experience. The presence of an audience is a defining feature because it is the
observers who perceive, interpret, and give meaning to the performance. An
audience’s reaction—be it applause, laughter, critique, or
interpretation—contributes to the complete nature of the performance, imbuing
it with a shared social reality. Hence, in this definition, the act of
performing carries an intention to convey a certain impression or communicate
meaning. Theories such as “reader-response theory” or “reception theory”
discuss how a text (or a performance) is not complete without its reception.
One could argue that a performance, like any event, occurs
regardless of observation. The actions of the performer, the expression of the
art, and the occurrence of the event are factual and exist independently of an
audience. The key distinction here is between the existence of the performance
and the validation or acknowledgement of it. Without an audience, the
validation through applause, criticism, or interpretation is absent, but the
performance as a sequence of actions still transpires. Even in an empty
theatre, a performer may deliver lines, an orchestra may play a symphony, and a
dancer may execute choreography; the physical and aesthetic actions do not
cease to exist because they are unobserved. However, while the tangible
mechanics of the performance may occur without an audience, the full spectrum
of what constitutes a performance—its energetic exchange, its emotional impact,
and its collective memory—is often thought to be co-created with those who
witness it.
Yet, the creation of performance without an audience is not
only possible but is already practiced in various forms within the arts:
artists like Marina Abramović, for instance, have explored the limits of what
constitutes performance and audience participation, sometimes engaging in acts
that are witnessed by very few or even by no one, at least at the time of the
initial act; and in the online digital space, it is commonplace for performance
to occur without an immediate physical audience. Consider a singer recording
vocals or an actor self-taping to camera—the eventual audience is remote,
separated by time, space, and medium, and yet the act of performance still
carries significant meaning and intent. The performances could be experienced
by an audience long after the fact, or hidden beneath the multitude of other
content and never seen. If nobody were to experience the recording—if the only
audience present was in the mind of the performer—is it true that a fully
actualised performance did not take place? The essence of the performances was
not in its reception, but in the act of expression: the performances were
created, executed, and fully realised without the presence of an external
audience. The audience here is not a required component for the validity of a
performance but rather a potential participant in a socially shared experience
that may or may not take place.
The external audience dynamics do affect the nature of the
performance, as well as its absence, but it is not necessary for the act of
performance. Indeed, the presence and disposition of an audience can have a
profound impact on the dynamics of a performance, affecting both the performers
and the collective meaning of the performance itself. This phenomenon has been
extensively studied across various disciplines including psychology, theatre
studies, and performance theory. Research often explores these effects through
the lenses of audience-performer dynamics, the psychology of performance, and
the sociology of group interactions. From a psychological perspective, the
seminal work of French sociologist Emile Durkheim on collective effervescence
describes the energy that emerges when a group of people, such as an audience,
comes together to participate in the same action. When performers are in front
of an audience, they can experience what psychologist Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi
terms as “flow”, a heightened state of focus and immersion in activities that
can enhance performance quality. Furthermore, the “audience effect”, a concept
often discussed in social psychology, specifically refers to the impact of an
audience on performance. Robert Zajonc’s work in this field identified the ways
in which the mere presence of others can enhance or inhibit performance,
depending on the complexity of the task and the skill level of the performer.
For well-practised tasks, an audience can enhance performance through increased
arousal; for less familiar tasks, however, this arousal can be detrimental. In
theatre studies, audience response is often viewed as a critical aspect. Susan
Bennett’s Theatre Audiences offers a comprehensive examination of the
reciprocal relationship between the audience and the performance. She outlines
how the audience’s reactions can influence the pacing, timing, and energy of a
performance as performers often adjust their delivery based on verbal and
non-verbal feedback. This dynamic interplay can transform the experience,
making each performance a unique event influenced by the specific audience in
attendance. Moreover, in his influential text The Empty Space, Peter
Brook discusses how an audience’s energy contributes to the creation of what he
describes as “immediate theatre”. According to Brook, the performer-audience
relationship is a crucial component that can turn the “deadly” theatre—where
there is no true communication—into a “live” one. The concept of audience
engagement and its effect on the performance is further elaborated by Baz
Kershaw in his work The Radical in Performance. Kershaw discusses how an
engaged audience can have a radicalising effect on performance, pushing the
boundaries of traditional performance and creating a more immersive and
interactive experience. In musical performance, John Sloboda’s research in The
Musical Mind touches upon how musicians might experience heightened levels
of anxiety or exhilaration when performing before an audience, which can, in
turn, affect their technical proficiency and emotional expression. This
interplay is significant in live music, where the audience’s reactions can
influence the performer’s interpretation and delivery of the music in real
time. From these perspectives, it becomes clear that an audience does not
passively consume a performance but actively shapes its unfolding through
complex psychological and social mechanisms. Each performance is therefore not
merely a presentation of a pre-prepared piece but a dynamic interaction between
performer and audience, with the audience’s responses continuously shaping the
course and quality of the performance.
However, it is possible for a performer to have an audience,
even when nobody is watching. This notion of a performer being the audience of
his or her own performance invites a rich philosophical exploration, touching
upon the concepts of self-awareness, and the phenomenology of experience.
Philosophical discourse offers a breadth of perspectives on the relationship
between the observer and the observed, as well as the subject-object dichotomy.
In the field of aesthetics, the work of philosophers like Arthur Danto in his
work The Transfiguration of the Commonplace can provide insight into the
relationship between performance and perception. Danto’s theories on art as the
embodiment of meaning suggest that a performer could very well be an audience
to the meanings and interpretations that arise within their own performance.
Each gesture, movement, or note in a performance can be reflective, carrying an
intention and interpretation that the performer is uniquely positioned to
understand and critique. The performer, then, becomes a sort of reflective
audience, engaging with the performance both as a creator and an interpreter of
meaning.
If a comedian makes a joke in an empty auditorium, does it
make a sound? It is often said that in stand-up, timing is everything. As it
turns out, when the audience is a row of empty seats, the timing is quite
flexible. However, whether it is a performance to one’s own shadow or to a
billion eager faces, the essence of the act, rather than the perception of the
expression, remains the same. When a performance is enacted without an external
audience, it becomes a private act, serving as a method of personal reflection
for the artist; but the performer is still engaged in the act of performing,
utilising their skills and perhaps even experiencing the same emotional and
physical exertion as they would in front of an external audience. If the self
can act as its own audience, then the solitude of one’s actions does not strip
them of their performative character. For some creators, such as me, the act of
performance is an intimate expression which serves as a form of
self-exploration, catharsis, or a means of working through ideas and emotions.
It’s here, in the sanctum of one’s mind, where the self-reflexive nature of
human consciousness creates a sort of inner theatre where our actions are
constantly up for review. The internal audience functions continuously, responding
to and influencing the performance.
A performer can be the audience of his or her own
performance, not in the literal sense of occupying two distinct spatial positions,
but rather in the phenomenological sense of experiencing oneself as both the
observer and the observed. This duality encapsulates the complex nature of
human consciousness and the intricate interplay between action and reflection.
In essence, the performer, through introspection and self-awareness, engages in
a dialogue with oneself, constantly interpreting and re-interpreting the
ongoing performance. From a phenomenological standpoint, particularly within
the framework established by Edmund Husserl, the idea of a performer as an
audience invokes the concept of “intentionality”, the notion that consciousness
is always the consciousness of something. In this context, a performer, even
while engaged in the act of performance, can have a dual intentionality where
he or she is both the subject directing the performance and simultaneously the
object of his or her own reflective consciousness. Husserl’s student, Martin
Heidegger, would perhaps interpret this through the lens of “Dasein”, which
underscores the idea of being-in-the-world where one’s existence is
fundamentally interconnected with the world; thus, a performer, by being an
audience to oneself, is actively shaping and being shaped by the very act of
performance.
For existentialists, if every action is a conscious choice,
we are, in essence, “performing” our lives for the most critical audience:
ourselves. Sartre’s notion of “bad faith”—the denial of this freedom and the
embrace of a fixed role—highlights the performativity of actions when they are
done to conform rather than to reflect one’s genuine choice. Sartre’s views
suggest that by becoming an audience to oneself, the performer engages in a
kind of self-observation that can either be an act of authenticity, recognising
oneself as the source of one’s actions, or an act of self-deception, where one
denies material agency. Within this existential frame, the notion of
authenticity is pivotal. The performance is not about creating a façade for
others but is intrinsically tied to the authentic choices that define our
being. Therefore, every action could be a performance if it is part of this
continuous existential project of self-definition. The actions themselves
become a narrative in the theatre of the self, where the individual not only
acts but observes, judges, and often reinterprets their actions in the quest
for meaning.
From a Jungian perspective, personal acts can be seen as
influenced by and potentially performing archetypal roles within our own
psyche. These acts, whether observed by others or not, are part of the fabric
of our collective unconscious experience. They connect us to universal human
themes and contribute to our personal narrative and the ongoing process of
psychological development and individuation. The performative aspect is not
necessarily about an audience of others but rather about the dialogue between
our conscious self and the archetypal forces within us. Carl Jung suggested
that archetypes represent universal, ancient symbols and images emanating from
the collective unconscious, serving as the psychological equivalents of
instinct. If we consider our personal acts as informed by these archetypes,
it’s possible to view our actions as being influenced by these shared human
narratives, which could be understood as a form of performance. When no
external audience is present, the archetypes within the collective unconscious
could act as an internal audience; for instance, if one’s actions align with
the hero archetype, one might unconsciously “perform” acts of bravery or
sacrifice, not for the sake of an external observer, but to satisfy an innate,
archetypal script. In performing actions when we are alone, we might
unconsciously be enacting certain archetypal patterns. This performance is not
for others but for oneself, or rather, for the archetypal structures embedded
within the psyche. Jung’s concept of individuation—the psychological process of
integrating the conscious with the unconscious, including the archetypes—could
be considered a performance in its own right. The process is an inward journey
that involves confronting internal archetypal figures and is often played out
through personal acts and choices, even when no one is watching.
In spiritual contexts, the idea of a divine observer alters
the understanding of performance and audience. In this context, God is the
ever-present audience. For those who hold this belief, the ultimate audience is
not earthly but spiritual—God, or a divine presence. This shifts the emphasis
from pleasing a human audience to performing in a way that aligns with divine
will or cosmic order. For such individuals, every action is a performance in
the sight of the divine, and this awareness can shape their choices and actions
profoundly. In Christianity, the idea of Coram Deo, which means “in the
presence of God”, encapsulates living one’s life as a performance before God in
every action. In the mystic traditions of Sufism, every act of love and beauty
can be seen as a performance that honours the divine. The dhikr (remembrance of
God) and the whirling dance of the dervishes are both performances meant to
unify the soul with the divine, transcending the earthly plane.
And so, the audience-performance question depends ultimately on the intent behind the performance. If the aim of the act is to be witnessed, to have a shared experience that communicates a message or evokes a collective emotional response, then, without an audience, the nature of the performance remains unfulfilled; conversely, if the purpose is for personal, psychological, or spiritual growth and self-expression, then the act of performing can be fully actualised without the need for external participants. Indeed, a self-actualising performer might argue that this form of performance is more true and pure because it is unpolluted by egoic desires or commercial and societal expectations; it is a performance for and with the artist’s own creative soul.
The phrase “All the world’s a stage”, famously penned by William Shakespeare in As You Like It, is a potent metaphor that encapsulates the idea that all of life is a performance, and that people are merely actors within it. Even when there seems to be no audience, the phrase implies that the mere act of living and interacting with the world is a performance in itself. According to Shakespeare’s metaphor, life’s performance continues irrespective of an observable audience because the “stage” of the world is ever-present. The metaphor is profound because, as can be derived from psychological and philosophical research, we are all performing our own stories envisaged in our minds. We embody these roles and, through them, engage with the narrative of our lives, seeking our version of a story’s resolution—be it peace, understanding, success, or reconciliation. In considering life as a form of art, the role of the individual can be seen as that of the artist, actively crafting his or her own life narrative, performance, and aesthetic. Life, in this light, becomes a canvas on which the aesthetics, themes, and structures of art are reproduced and reinterpreted, with each person both as the artist and the audience of their own existence.